Probabilistic Inferences
Recall that means that is the premise and is the conclusion. Of course, most arguments have more than one premise. In this section, think of as the conjunction of all the premises of an argument. For example, an instance of Modus Ponens is the argument with premises and , and conclusion . In this notation, we represent this argument as . Sometimes it is important to list the premises separately. We use a comma to separate the premises. For instance, we might write Modus Ponens as .
Consider an argument . We have introduced three ways to evaluate how supports :
- is (deductively) valid: There is no truth value assignment that makes true and false.
- Given a stochastic truth table, evidentially supports : .
- Given a stochastic truth table, is positively relevant to : .
There is an important difference between item 1 and items 2 and 3. There is only one truth table for an argument , but there are infinitely many stochastic truth tables. Whether evidentially supports (resp. is positively relevant to) depends on the stochastic truth table. One consequence of this is that for atomic propositions and , while (the argument is not valid), there are stochastic truth tables in which evidentially supports (resp. is positively relevant to) . For instance, use the following interactive stochastic truth table to find the following:
- A stochastic truth table where evidentially supports and is positively relevant to .
- A stochastic truth table where does not evidentially support and is not positively relevant to .
- A stochastic truth table where evidentially supports and is not positively relevant to .
- A stochastic truth table where does not evidentially support and is positively relevant to .
In the remainder of this section, we identify some interesting differences between valid arguments and inductively strong arguments.
Non-Monotonicity
We have already observed that valid arguments are monotonic:
For all , and , if , then .
That is, any valid argument remains valid with the addition of any premise. It is not hard to find examples of seemingly strong arguments that are no longer as strong with the addition of certain premises. For instance, the following is a good argument:
Tweety is a bird. So, Tweety flies.
While this is not a valid argument, it is an inductively strong argument. However, if you learn that Tweety is a penguin, then the conclusion that Tweety flies no longer follows from the premises. This type of non-monotonicity is typical of probabilistic reasoning. The first observation is that evidential support is not monotonic.
There are formulas , and and a stochastic truth table such that evidentially supports , but conditional on , does not evidentially supports .
To illustrate this phenomenon, find a stochastic truth table for , and such that:
- (so evidentially supports )
- (so does not evidentially support )
and
Conjunction Fallacy
We start with a famous reasoning experiment from the Nobel prize winning psychologists Amos Tversky and Dan Kahneman. Suppose that you are told the following about Linda:
Linda is 31 years old, single, outspoken, and very bright. She majored in philosophy. As a student, she was deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, and also participated in anti-nuclear demonstrations.
Which is more probable?
- Linda is a bank teller
- Linda is a bank teller and is active in the feminist movement.
Most people respond that 2 is more probable than 1. Let mean that "Linda is a bank teller" and mean "Linda is active in the feminist movement". Then, anyone who reports that 2 is more probable than 1, is saying that . However, this contradicts the laws of probability: Since is a tautology, in any stochastic truth table . In fact, people that respond that 2 is more probable than 1 seem to be violating the following stronger principle of probabilistic reasoning:
For all , and and all stochastic truth tables, if is a tautology, then
Let represent the evidence that you are told about Linda (e.g., she was a philosophy major, deeply concerned with issues of discrimination and social justice, etc.). Then, according to the above observation, . So if evidentially supports , then must evidentially support . More generally, we have the following:
For all formulas , and and stochastic truth tables, if is a tautology and evidentially supports , then evidentially supports .
One explanation for why many people say that 2 is more probable than 1 is that they are evaluating the relevance of the evidence to the two possibilities rather than measuring the evidential support of the evidence to the and . Unlike evidential support, positive relevance is not preserved under tautological implications.
There are formulas , and and a stochastic truth table such that is a tautology, is positively relevant to , but is not positively relevant to .
To illustrate, finish filling in the following stochastic truth table so that:
- ( is positively relevant to )
- ( is negatively relevant to )
- Lecture
- Slides
Sure-Thing Principle
In order to show that something follows from a disjunction you must show that it follows from each disjunct. That is, the following is an important principle of valid inferences:
For all formulas , and , if and , then .
A special case of the above observation is the following: If and , then must be a tautology. To see why this is true, suppose that and . Then, every truth value assignment falls into one of two categories:
The truth value assignment makes true. Then, since , the truth value assignment makes true
The truth value assignment makes false. Then, since , the truth value assignment makes true.
Since is true in every truth value assignment, is a tautology. Can we adapt the above reasoning to show evidential support and positive relevance?
The first observation is that the above reasoning can be used to show evidential support between two formulas. We start with the following preliminary observation:
If evidentially supports and evidentially supports , then is probable: For all formulas and and all stochastic truth tables, if and , then .
More generally, we can show that evidentially supports by demonstrating that both of the following are true:
- evidentially supports conditional on ; and
- evidentially supports conditional on .
The first statement means that and the second statements means that . So, the following justifies the above claim.
For all formulas , and and all stochastic truth tables,
if and ,
then .
The situation is more complicated with positive relevance. We want to show that if
- is positively relevant to conditional on and
- is positively relevant to conditional on ,
then is positively relevant to .
The first complication is that " is positively relevant to conditional on " can be interpreted in two ways:
Using the second interpretation, we can adapt the above reasoning to positive relevance, called the conditional sure-thing principle.
For all formulas , and and all stochastic truth tables,
if and ,
then .
Surprisingly, there is no analogous result when " is positively relevant to conditional on " uses the first interpretation:
There are formulas , and and a stochastic truth table, such that
- ,
- , but
- .
The failure of the unconditional sure-thing principle is related to a well-known issue in statistics known as Simpson's Paradox. Suppose that a University is hiring in Philosophy and Mathematics, and that 13 men and 13 women in total apply for jobs.
In the Mathematics department, 5 men and 8 women apply for jobs. Suppose that 1 of the men is hired and 2 of the women are hired. The success rate favors women over men:
In the Philosophy department, 8 men and 5 women apply for jobs. Suppose that 6 of the men are hired and 4 of the women are hired. The success rate favors women over men:
So, in both departments, the success rate favors women over men. However, when we determine the overall success rate, the inequalities reverse: Overall, 7 of the 13 men were hired and 6 out of the 13 women were hired. This means that the overall success rate for men is better than for women:
How can it be that each Department favors women applicants, and yet overall men fare better than women?
See this video for a discussion of this.
Practice Questions
- Is valid? Does evidentially supports ? Is positively relevant to ?
- Is valid? Does evidentially supports ? Is positively relevant to ?
- Is valid? Does evidentially supports ? Is positively relevant to ?
- Can you find a stochastic truth table for , and such that evidentially supports , but does not evidentially support ?
- Can you find a stochastic truth table for , and such that is positively relevant to , is positively relevant to , but is not positively relevant to ?